Diogenes or On Virtue

Diogenes or On Virtue (Ancient Greek: Διογένης ἢ περὶ ἀρετῆς, romanizedDiogenēs e peri aretēs, Oration 8 in modern corpora) is a speech delivered by Dio Chrysostom between AD 82 and 96,[1] which is presented as a speech delivered by the Cynic philosopher Diogenes of Sinope at the Isthmian Games. It presents the superiority of a Cynic lifestyle, through a comparison with the professional athlete and a revisionist account of the life of Heracles. The oration forms a pair with the Isthmian Oration, which continues the story of Diogenes' visit to the Isthmian Games with many of the same themes.

Background

Statue of an unknown Cynic philosopher from the Capitoline Museums in Rome.[2]

The fourth-century BC philosopher Diogenes founded the Cynic school of philosophy after being exiled from his hometown of Sinope. He was famous for his very ascetic lifestyle, living outdoors and going without shoes or clothes. Dio Chrysostom was exiled by the Emperor Domitian in AD 82 and, according to his 13th oration, On his Banishment, he then adopted the guise of a Cynic philosopher and travelled Greece and the Black Sea, delivering orations like this one.

Summary

The speech consists of an introduction (sections 1-10), a speech supposedly delivered by Diogenes at the Isthmian Games (11-35), and a brief conclusion (36).

The introduction explains how Diogenes came to Athens and met Antisthenes, the founder of Cynicism and contrasts Antisthenes' mastery of virtuous doctrine with Diogenes' mastery of a virtuous lifestyle (1-4). Dio then recounts how Diogenes moved to Corinth after Antisthenes' death and made a habit of attending the Isthmian Games held there, with an extended metaphor of the philosopher as a doctor for spiritual illness (5-8). At the games, sightseers flock to see sophists and spectacles, among which Diogenes draws large crowds, who mostly find his presentation too challenging (9-10)

Diogenes' speech (11-35) contains three parts. In the first part (11-19), Diogenes explains that he has come to the games "not to watch but to compete" (11). His "rivals" are not athletes but "hardships" (Ancient Greek: πόνοι, romanizedponoi), such hunger, thirst, cold, exile, and disreputable things. He explains how this competition is superior to the athletic competitions of the games and how he is superior to the athletes who compete only from time-to-time at games festivals and for useless prizes, while he is competing always and for "happiness and virtue" (13-16). Diogenes explains that the only way to defeat hardships is by fighting them constantly, fearlessly, and totally:

If one accepts hardships with disdain and approaches them enthusiastically, they are entirely powerless against him, but if he holds back and gives way to them, they seem entirely too big and fierce for him.

— Dio Chrysostom Or. 8.18

This is illustrated by a number of similes - facing hardship is like scaring off a fierce dog, fighting a boxing match, putting out a flame with one's tongue, or fighting the pancratium (17-19).

In the second part (20-26), Diogenes explains the best strategy for meeting a second opponent: "pleasure" (Ancient Greek: ἡδονή, romanizedhēdonē). Here the approach is the opposite: pleasure must be avoided altogether, since any engagement with pleasure leads to defeat (24). Whereas the battle with hardship is like the combat of the heroic warriors in Homer's Iliad, pleasure is like Circe from the Odyssey, who needed only the slightest moment to transform Odysseus' men into pigs and wolves.

Fragmentary Roman-period statue of Heracles wrestling the Nemean lion, found at Isthmia.

The third part of Diogenes' speech (27-35) is a revisionist account of the labours of Heracles, presenting him as a paragon of the Cynic lifestyle, rather than the athletic one. Heracles, like Diogenes, was ignored in favour of flashier heroes in life, only receiving the honours he deserved after death (27-28). Heracles' physique was not the overly fleshy one of a contemporary athlete, which required a special diet and plenty of rest to maintain. Instead, he was alert and light "like a lion" (30). Such a man could not have been controlled by a non-entity like Eurystheus, who gave Heracles his labours in the traditional version of the myth (29, 34). Heracles' ability to resist hardship allowed him to easily kill luxurious tyrants like Diomedes of Thrace, Geryon, and Busiris (31-32). Heracles' resistance to pleasure allowed him to take Hippolyta's girdle (32) and meant that he had no need of the golden apples of the Hesperides (34). Prometheus was actually a sophist, who was freed from his errors by Heracles' example (33). His cremation in old age was a self-immolation intended to demonstrate his indifference to heat and cold (35). Finally, Heracles cleaned the stables of Augeas to demonstrate that he was not above disreputable work (35).

The brief conclusion (36) states that the crowd was initially swayed by Diogenes' words but then he, inspired by the story of the Augean stables with which he finished his oration, sat down and "did something disreputable" (probably defecating),[3][4] and then they dismissed him as crazy and departed.

And all the sophists went back to making a ruckus, like frogs in a pond, unaware of the water snake.

— Dio Chrysostom Or. 8.36

Analysis

At the time when the speech was delivered, Dio was in exile and we are probably meant to see parallels between his accounts of Diogenes and Heracles and his own situation. In particular, the inability of the mythical despot Eurystheus to truly control the wandering Heracles may have been intended as a comment on Domitian's inability to control Dio.[1] However, Dio's adoption of the persona of Diogenes is also a method of distancing himself from the contents of his oration - "presenting advice without committing himself to it unequivocally."[5]

Dio builds on a tradition of seeing Heracles as a model of virtue and a role model for a philosopher, which goes back to the fourth century BC. Within this tradition, Heracles was particularly closely associated with the Cynics in Roman-period literature, probably because both the mendicant Cynic and Heracles on his labours wandered throughout the world. Diogenes Laertius reports that Diogenes the Cynic had compared himself to Heracles because they both "put nothing before freedom" and Epictetus named him as the first Cynic hero. Dio also discusses Heracles as a role model in On Kingship I (52-84), where the young Heracles must choose between Royalty and Tyranny, and in On the Story of Deïaneira, where Heracles' death is a result of his failure to maintain the Cynic lifestyle.[3]

Dio's presentation of athleticism in this oration is very negative.[6] Jason König draws connections to negative depictions of athletic training in Lucian's Anacharsis and Seneca's Letters 15 and 80.[7] In this oration, as in those authors, athletics is presented as an empty waste of time, which produces a 'soft' body that requires constant monitoring and is incapable of facing hardship.[8] By contrast, in Melancomas I and II, Dio presents athletic training as a model for the Cynic's pursuit of virtue.[9]

The ending, in which Diogenes sits down and defecates in public, strongly undercuts the main speech. This contrast between speech and framing narrative is a common feature of Dio's orations and may be part of the same distancing tactics mentioned above.[5] Many opponents of Cynicism in the Roman period pointed to shameless behaviour like public defecation, by Cynics in general and Diogenes in particular, in their criticism of the doctrine.[10] Dio might be suggesting that people who focus on that behaviour miss the more important doctrinal points about the virtuous life.

Editions

  • Hans von Arnim, Dionis Prusaensis quem uocant Chrysostomum quae exstant omnia (Berlin, 1893–1896).
  • Cohoon, J. W. (1932). Dio Chrysostom, I, Discourses 1–11. Princeton: Harvard University Press, Loeb Classical Library. ISBN 9780674992832. Retrieved 4 January 2023.

References

  1. ^ a b Cohoon 1932, p. 375.
  2. ^ Christopher H. Hallett, (2005), The Roman Nude: Heroic Portrait Statuary 200 BC–AD 300, p. 294. Oxford University Press
  3. ^ a b Stafford 2013, pp. 126–127.
  4. ^ Krueger 1996, p. 230.
  5. ^ a b König 2005, p. 140.
  6. ^ König 2005, p. 141.
  7. ^ König 2005, p. 136-138, 157.
  8. ^ König 2005, p. 136-142.
  9. ^ König 2005, p. 142.
  10. ^ Krueger 1996.

Bibliography

  • Brancacci, Aldo (2002). "Dio, Socrates, and Cynicism". In Swain, Simon (ed.). Dio Chrysostom: Politics, Letters, and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 240–260. ISBN 978-0-19-925521-4.
  • Brenk, Frederick E. (2002). "Dio on the Simple and Self-Sufficient Life". In Swain, Simon (ed.). Dio Chrysostom: Politics, Letters, and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 261–278. ISBN 978-0-19-925521-4.
  • König, Jason (2005). Athletics and Literature in the Roman Empire. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521838450.
  • Krueger, Derek (1996). "The Bawdy and Society: The Shamelessness of Diogenes in Roman Imperial Culture". In Branham, R. Bracht; Goulet-Cazé, Marie-Odile (eds.). The Cynics: The Cynic Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy. University of California Press. pp. 222–239. ISBN 978-0-520-21645-7.
  • Stafford, Emma (2013). Herakles. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-51926-0.
  • Full text of the speech on LacusCurtius
  • v
  • t
  • e
  1. On Kingship I
  2. On Kingship II
  3. On Kingship III
  4. On Kingship IV
  5. A Libyan Myth
  6. Diogenes or On Tyranny
  7. Euboean Oration
  8. Diogenes or On Virtue
  9. Diogenes or the Isthmian Oration
  10. Diogenes or on Servants
  11. Trojan Oration
  12. Olympic Oration or On Man's First Conception of God
  13. In Athens, on his Banishment
  14. On Slavery and Freedom I
  15. On Slavery and Freedom II
  16. On Pain and Distress of Spirit
  17. On Covetousness
  18. On Training for Public Speaking
  19. On the Author's Fondness for Listening
  20. On Retirement
  21. On Beauty
  22. Concerning Peace and War
  23. The Wise Man is Happy
  24. On Happiness
  25. On the Guiding Spirit
  26. On Deliberation
  27. On Symposia
  28. Melancomas II
  29. Melancomas I
  30. Charidemus
  31. Rhodian Oration
  32. To the Alexandrians
  33. First Tarsian Oration
  34. Second Tarsian Oration
  35. Oration Delivered in Celaenae in Phrygia
  36. Borysthenitic Oration
  37. Corinthian Oration*
  38. On Concord with the Nicaeans
  39. On Concord in Nicaea
  40. On Concord with Apameia
  41. To the Apameians
  42. Lecture in his Native City
  43. Political Oration in his Native City
  44. Of Friendship for his Native Land
  45. In Defence of his Relations with Prusa
  46. Against Mistreatment by his Fellow Citizens
  47. His Efforts to Beautify Prusa
  48. Political Oration in the Assembly
  49. Declining Office as Archon
  50. In Defence of his Record
  51. In Reply to Diodorus
  52. An Appraisal of the Tragic Triad
  53. On Homer
  54. On Socrates
  55. On Homer and Socrates
  56. On Kingship V
  57. Homer’s Portrayal of Nestor
  58. A Dialogue Between Achilles and Cheiron
  59. Philoctetes, a Paraphrase
  60. On the Story of Deïaneira
  61. Chryseïs
  62. On Kingship and Tyranny
  63. On Fortune I
  64. On Fortune II
  65. On Fortune III
  66. On Reputation
  67. On Popular Opinion
  68. On Opinion
  69. On Virtue
  70. On Philosophy
  71. On the Philosopher
  72. On Personal Appearance
  73. On Trust
  74. On Distrust
  75. On Law
  76. On Custom
  77. On Envy
  78. On Wealth
  79. On Freedom
  80. Encomium on Hair